Formulaic Comparisons: Stopping the Charter at the Statutory Human Rights Gate

AuthorAndrea Wright
Pages409-441

twelve
Formulaic Comparisons:
      
 
Andrea Wright1
A. INTRODUCTION
is paper examines the emergence of another troubling trend in statu-
tory human rig hts jurisprudence: the increasing reliance on and misuse
of rigid comparative formulas. Statutory human rights tribunals and
reviewing courts are frequently neglecting or d isplacing the broad and
adaptable O’Malley test — the agship test for a prima facie case of dis-
crimination — in favour of restrictive comparator-group analyses, and re-
ductive tests that require comparative evidence in order to meet the prima
facie burden. A principal source of this trend is the ascendancy of compara-
tive formulas i n Charter jurisprudence. ese formulas cause claimants
to thread their discrimination experiences through templates that are ill-
tting and rig id, and that oen operate like forma l-equality analyses. e
result i s oen the de-contextualization of the complaint, and the denia l
of substantive equality. e O’Malley test does not require such formulaic
rigidity, and its application in statutory human rights jurisprudence should
be revitalized . Indeed, the O’Malley test , like many other governing prin-
ciples of statutory human rights jurisprudence, reects a conceptualization
of equa lity that focuses on the ourishing of every individual in all her
or his pa rticularity, not on formal istic comparisons of societal groups. Its
reinvigoration is therefore all the more imperative.
Specically, this paper rst reviews two methodologies increasingly be-
ing applied by statutory human rights tribunals: comparator-group anal-
     
yses, and the Shakes/Israeli test. It exa mines their eects, par ticularly in
contrast to the analysis that the neglected O’Malley test aords. It posits
that the comparator-group test requires ar ticial and precarious compari-
sons with “others,” which look and operate like formal-equality analyses,
lead to poor choices of “comparator groups,” and oen neglect the essential
question of the discrimination complaint — what position the claimant
would have been in were it not for the gravamen of the complaint. e pa-
per next examines the perils of the Shakes/Israeli test, which, while easing
a claimant’s burden in some ways, requires the claimant to adduce evidence
of the treatment or qual ications of others. is is evidence which is usu-
ally not within the complainant’s control, is oen imbued with the same
hidden discriminatory norms that are impugned in the rst place, and most
importantly, takes on conclusory status to the exclusion of the vast scope of
potential evidence that might otherwise e stablish a discrimination claim.
Fact patterns of discrimination are in nitely diverse, and there should be
as many avenues to establishing a prima facie case of discrimination as there
are manifestations of discrimination.
is paper posits that the roomy O’Malley test a llows for such plente-
ous consideration of discrimi nation complaints, in all their variety; while
the formulaic use of rigid comparative tests reduces a discrimination fact
pattern to a thread of itself, a thread which must be woven through narrow
comparative-formula templates if a complaint is to succeed. e result is of-
ten formalist analysis, the eacement of the gravamen of the complaint, the
de-contextualizing of a claimant’s experience, and the denial of substantive
equality. e continued application of these comparative formulas threat-
ens the gainful equa lity framework that the O’Malley test aords.
is paper therefore urges steadfast application of the O’Malley test in
statutory human rig hts cases, whatever the formula ic, comparative trends
in the Cha rter context. It questions the Charter proposition that equa lity
is necessari ly comparative, and hig hlights furt her aws of such a concep-
tualization, including the abstractionist, essential ist, and contradictory
premise that a historical ly-disadvantaged g roup can be tidily compared
to an identiable and historically-advantaged “other” group. It posits that
while comparisons with the conditions of others may be the long-estab-
lished convention of equality discourse, they should at most be probative
of an ideal condition, not conclusor y. It urges a conceptualization of equal-
ity a s the attainment of particularized idea ls, not comparative ones; and
discusses numerous statutory human rights principles and cases that apply
twelve•  
individualized, unipolar considerations of a claimant’s circumstance, such
as Meio rin a nd Brooks. It concludes that as long as Charter jurisprudence
rigidly conceptualizes equal ity as comparative, and as long as statutory hu-
man rights jurisprudence plenteously conceptualizes equality as the attain-
ment of societal conditions that allow the ourishing of every individual in
all her or his pa rticularity, it is the latter framework that oers the g reater
potential for the achievement of substantive equa lity in Canada. e
O’Malley test, and other statutory human rig hts constructs, must there-
fore be reinvigorated, and the Charter’s increasing comparative formulism
should be stopped at the statutory human rights gate.
B. COMPARATIVE METHODOLOGIES IN STATUTORY HUMAN RIGHTS
JURISPRUDENCE: A SURVEY OF SOME PROMINENT AND/OR RECENT
EXAMPLES OF THEIR ERRONEOUS APPLICATION
Statutory human rights case s in the employment context can roughly be
categorized into three types of complaints: () complaints that allege that a
rule, standard, or practice in t he employment context was discriminatory,
or that the denial of a benet or service was discriminatory; () complaints
that a hiring, promotion, or dismissal decision was discrim inatory; and ()
complaints of harassment or other discriminatory conduct. e governing
test for whether a complaint of discrimination has been made out — the
O’Malley test — is broad and adaptable enough to be applied in all three
categories of cases. It states:
e complainant must rst establish a prima facie case of d iscrimina-
tion; that is, one that covers t he allegations made and which, if they are
believed, is complete and sucient to justify a verdict in the complainant’s
favour in the absence of an answer from the respondent. e burden then
shis to the respondent to provide a reasonable explanation for the oth-
erwise discriminatory rule/practice/conduct. If the respondent provides
such an expla nation, the complainant has the ev identiary burden of dem-
onstrating that the explanation provided was merely a pretext and that the
true motivation behind the employer’s actions was in fact discriminatory.
In its generalit y, the O’Malley test appropriately oers to complain-
ants, who would otherwise have a “herculean” task, t he chance to prove
a prima facie ca se of discri mination in a vital ly large number of ways:
through indi rect evidence, through “subtle scent(s),” throug h agg regated
pieces of evidence, through clumsy sums of evidence, through considera-

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT