Consideration and Form

AuthorJohn D. Mccamus
ProfessionProfessor of Law. Osgoode Hall Law School, York University
Pages211-274
CHAP TER 7
CONSIDER ATION
AND FORM
A. INTRODUCTION
The giving and, indeed, exchanging of promises or undertakings is
a pervasive feature of our commerci al and social lives. A question of
central importance for the law of contracts is to articulate a basis for
distinguishing between those promises that should properly attract the
attention of the legal system as enforceable promises and those that
should not. Although an argument could be fashioned on the basi s of
moral precepts that al l promises should be considered binding as a m at-
ter of honour, few observers would suggest that all promises should be
legally enforceable regardless of how rash and improvident they might
have been and regardless of the setting, be it commercial or non-com-
mercial, in which the promise was made. In the English common law
tradition, two criter ia of enforceability or rules for the recognition of
enforceable promis es have developed.
The basic principle is that promises will be enforced only if they
form part of a bargain. The doctr ine of consideration holds that to be
enforceable, a promise must be purcha sed in the sense of being given
in return for something of va lue provided by t he promisee or, as is sa id,
for “good consideration.” The enforcement of bargains obviously plays
an important role in the functioning of a modern credit economy. It is
easily seen, therefore, that a strong rationale exists for the enforcement
of ba rgains . What is less cle ar, howeve r, is whether t he doctr ine of con -
211
THE LAW OF CONTR ACTS212
sideration or, as it is sometimes called, the bargain theory, successfully
identif‌i es the proper line of demarcation between t hose promises th at
should be considered enforceable by the legal system and those that
should not. Indeed, the doctrine of consideration has attracted much
criticism over the years. In the present ch apter, after providing an ac-
count of various aspects of the application of the doctrine, we w ill re-
turn to consider the prosp ects for its reform.
The second rule of recognition for enforceable promises re sts on
the formal trappings within which t he undertaking i s given. Thus,
centurie s prior to the development of the doctrine of consideration,
the English legal system recogn ized as enforceable those promi ses that
were made in the form of sealed instruments. Although the manner or
method of sealing in struments has evolved over time, the basic prin-
ciple that a promise given under sea l is enforceable simply because
of the formal manner in which t he undertaking h as been given has
persisted. For much of the early history of the doctrine, the execu-
tion of an instr ument under seal involved the melting of some wax or
other adhesive substance on the instrument upon which an i mpression
of a seal or signet ring or other identif‌i er of the party executing the
instrument could be m ade. The general enforceability of inst ruments
executed in this f ashion appears to stretch back as far, at least, as the
fourteenth century.1 In an essentially pre-literate society, it is easily
seen that the aff‌i xing of the seals constituted, in effect, a form of sig-
nature. Under contemporary practice, of course, it is commonplace for
people to execute agreements by placing their handwritten signature
on the document. There is thus no practical necessity for the use of
seals as an equivalent of signature. Nonetheless, the practice of sealing
instrument s and of enforcing them simply by reason of their formal
nature continues in ma ny common law jurisdictions to the present day.
The contemporary version of the sealed in strument ty pically involves
the aff‌i xing of a small round piece of red-coloured adhesive paper or
“wafer” next to the signature of the promisor. Although the solemnity
of the act of sealing has thus obviously declined over the centur ies, the
execution of instrument s under seal nonetheless remain s a useful al-
ternative to considerat ion as it provides a device by which non-bargain
promises can be rendered en forceable. At the same time, the decline
in the solemnity of the form a nd the fact that, outside the legal profes-
sion, there is unlikely to be w idespread understanding of the legal sig-
nif‌i cance of the typical contemporary seal, the doctrine has attracted
1 See A.W.B. Simpson, A History of the Common La w of Contract (Oxford: Claren-
don Press, 1975) at 9–52.
Consideration a nd Form 213
much criticism in the modern era. After examini ng the contemporary
doctrine relating to sealed instruments, then, we will return to con-
sider contemporary justif‌i cations for doctrine s justifying enforceability
on the basis of requirements of formal ity and possible measures for the
reform of current formality doct rine.
The history of the development of the doctrine of consideration
and its ultimate emergence in its modern form in the late-eighteenth
and nineteenth centuries is both complicated and the subject of much
academic invest igation and controversy.2 This complex story can not be
told here. We may note, however, that along the way var ious alternative
formulations of the basic rule of recognition were rejected. Thus, for a
time, English courts and, in particula r, Lord Mansf‌i eld, toyed with the
idea that contracts recorded in w riting could be enforceable even in the
absence of consideration. In the well-known c ase of Pillans and Rose v.
Van Mierop & Hopkins,3 Lord Mansf‌i eld offered the controversial view
that the rationale of the consider ation doctrine was merely ev identiary
in nature and that other evidence of contractual intent, such as t he re-
cording of the agreement in wr iting, should suff‌i ce, even in the absence
of consideration. More generally, it was his view that the abs ence of
consideration should not defeat agreements between merchants, both
formal and informal. A few years later, however, the House of Lords, in
its 1778 decision in Rann v. Hughes,4 rejected as erroneous Mansf‌i eld’s
suggestion that the fact of a writing eliminated the need for considera-
tion. Nonetheless, the fact that the doctrine of consideration renders
unenforceable some seriously intended promises, es pecially those
given by merchants, bec ause of the absence of consideration, continues
to inspire contemporary cr iticism of the doctrine and may, indeed, lead
to its reform.
Further, English law has rejected t he idea that the fact th at a prom-
ise has been followed by substant ial detrimental rel iance thereon by the
promisee should render the promise enforceable, at least in cases where
the reliance was foresee able or, indeed, intended by the promisor.5 Again,
however, the fact that foreseeable detrimental reliance on a promise w ill
not have the effect of rendering the promis e enforceable persists as a point
2 See, for example, Simp son,above note 1; S.J. Stoljar, A History of Contract at
Common La w (Canberra: Australian National University Press, 1975).
3 (1765), 3 Burr. 1663, 97 E.R. 1035 (K.B.). See K. Teeven, “Mansf‌i eld’s Reform of
Consideration i n Light of the Origins of t he Doctrine” (1991) 21 Memphis State
U.L. Rev. 669. See also Simpson, ibid . at 617–19.
4 (1778), 4 Brown P.C. 27, 2 E.R. 18 (H.L.).
5 For discussion of e arly intimations of a reli ance doctrine, see Teeven, above
note 3 at 670–72.

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT