Judicial Acceptance of Limits on Rights

AuthorKent Roach
Pages155-173
155
Judicial Acceptance
of
Limits
on
Rights
Many
people probably nodded with agreement when they read
Justice
Bastarache's
comments that
the
Court
"was maybe seen
as
being undu-
ly
favourable
to the
native position
in all
cases,
and
that
it
sort
of has an
agenda
for
extending these rights,
and
that
it has no
concern
for the
rights
of
others
...
you
have fishermen
who are not
very wealthy
and
whose
rights might have been [perceived
to
have been] overridden
by
the
rights
of
natives
too
easily
by the
court."1
People tend
to
think
of
courts
as a
place where rights trump over
all
other
interests.
If
judges
decide
what constitutes
a
right
and if
rights
are
absolute, then
the
Court
will
override competing rights
and
interests.
And
there
are
examples
of
cases
in
which
the
Supreme
Court
has
appeared
to be
oblivious
to
com-
peting
rights.
How
else
can you
explain
its
decisions
to
strike down
restrictions
on
Sunday shopping, tobacco advertising,
and
some
of its
more
controversial decisions recognizing
the
rights
of the
accused
and
of
Aboriginal people?
Critics
of
judicial activism
fear
that judges will impose absolute
rights
on
society without regard
to
competing rights
and
social interests.
Conservative
critics tend
to
worry about
the
inflation
of
rights, group
rights
and the
rights
of the
accused. They
fear
that legalistic
and
absolute
rights
talk will make
it
difficult,
if not
impossible,
to
accept
the
compromises that
are
often
necessary
in a
functioning
and
civil democ-
racy.
Progressive critics worry that judges will impose
a
liberal
and
indi-
vidualistic
view
of
rights that conceives
of the
state
as the
enemy,
a
view
that leaves little room
for the
promotion
of a
sense
of
social responsi-
bility
and
duty. Much
of the
anxiety
about judicially enforced
rights
comes
from
the
common opinion that rights
are
absolute "trumps."
The
First
Amendment
of the
American
Bill
of
Rights
supports this absolutist
view
of
rights when
it
declares that Congress shall make
no law
abridg-
ing
freedom
of
speech.
As
I
suggest throughout
this
book, however,
the
Canadian
Charter
of
Rights
and
Freedoms
is
fundamentally
different
from
the
American
Bill
of
Rights.
Instead
of the
First Amendment,
we
have
a
more modest sec-
tion
1,
which provides that
the
Charter
"guarantees
the
rights
and
free-
doms
set out in
it,"
but
subject
"to
such reasonable limits prescribed
by
law
as can be
demonstrably
justified
in a
free
and
democratic society."
This approach draws
on the
modern experience
of
allowing necessary
Chapter 9
156
PART
2: THE
EXTENT
OF
JUDICIAL
ACTIVISM
and
proportional limits
on
many rights,
but
generalizes
it by
allowing
courts
to
accept limits
on
every right
for a
broad range
of
reasons.
If a
good
idea gets copied, section
1 is a
good idea.
It has
been
duplicated
in
recent bill
of
rights
in New
Zealand,
Israel,
and
South
Africa,
and the
Supreme Court
of
Canada
has
invented
a
process
of
justifying limita-
tions
on
Aboriginal
and
treaty rights even though section
1
does
not
apply
to
those rights. Critics
of
judicial activism
in
Canada must come
to
grips with
the
brooding omnipresence that
the
limitation provision
casts
on
constitutional rights.
It
will
not do to
pretend that this
is
America,
where once
a
court
has
defined
a
right
it is
often
absolute
and
final.
Cries that
my
rights have been violated play better
on the
nightly
news than
in
Canadian courts.
In
court, judges will
ask
whether
the
gov-
ernment
had a
good
reason
for
violating rights.
Section
1 of the
Charter
does
not
mean that
the
Court
accepts
all
limits
on
rights.
The
legislature must articulate
its
desire
to
limit rights,
so
unelected
officials
such
as
police
officers,
for
example, cannot take
it
on
themselves
to
limit rights without statutory authorization.
The
requirement
that
the
legislature
make clear
statements
when
it
intends
to
limit rights
follows
common
law
traditions
and
enhances democracy.
It
requires candour and, ideally, legislative
and
public debate about
the
limits placed
on
rights.
In
addition, governments also must
justify
limi-
tations
on
rights
by
showing that they were aimed
at an
important
objec-
tive,
that
the
limitation advances that
objective,
that there were
not
other less drastic
but
reasonable alternatives
to
advance
the
objective,
and
that
the
overall benefit
of the
limitation
in
advancing
the
objective
outweighs
the
costs
of
infringing
the
right.
The
ability
of
governments
to
justify laws
that
violate rights
under
section
1 of the
Charter
promotes
a
dialogue between courts
and
legislatures, with
the
courts asking
why
rights need
to be
violated,
and the
legislature explaining why. Section
1,
not
section
33, is the
true engine
of
dialogue under
the
Charter.
Sunday
Shopping
Much
about
the
role
and
evolution
of
section
1 of the
Charter
can be
understood
by
recalling
a
time,
one
that seems increasing distant
and
quaint,
in
which there
was
controversy over whether people could shop
on
Sunday.
Today,
most
of us are
happy
to
find
any
time
in our
hectic
lives
to buy
groceries
and
other
necessities,
let
alone worry about
the
religious significance
of
Sunday
or
whether Sunday shopping will dis-
rupt
a
common rest
day to be
shared with
families
and
friends.
The
first
challenge
to
Sunday closing laws
was
brought
by a
Calgary
drug store,
Big M
Drug
Mart,
which
was
charged under
the
fed-
eral
Lord's
Day Act for
selling groceries
on
Sunday.
As its
name implied,

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT