Charter Rights in the Criminal Process

AuthorHon. Robert J. Sharpe/Kent Roach
ProfessionCourt of Appeal for Ontario- Faculty of Law University of Toronto
Pages234-275
CHAP TER 14
CHARTER
R IGHT S IN
THE CRIMINAL PROCESS
The Charter of Rights and Freedoms has had a profound impact in the
area of criminal law. Charter claims are routinely asserted in criminal
proceedings. There have been thousa nds of cases decided by the courts
involving detailed considerat ion of investigative techniques, pre-tr ial
procedures, and the trial process itsel f. We offer here a sampling of
some of the most significant is sues that are rai sed by the Charter.
One way to examine the impact of the Charter is to use t he ab-
stract models of the cri minal process first put forward by the Amer ican
scholar Herbert Packer to assess t he influence of the American Bill of
Rights on the cr iminal justice system.1 The first is the “cri me control
model” in which the focus of the criminal justice system is to find and
punish the guilt y through efficient police and prosecutorial work, usu-
ally leading to a gui lty plea. The second is the “due process” model in
which the focus is on controlling t he exercise of police powers through
an elaborate series of procedural guarantees, violation of which results
in the release of the accus ed regardless of guilt or in nocence. The Ca-
nadian criminal just ice system, in common with the systems of other
liberal democracies, has always exhibited features of both models.
Crime control is bound to be a central feature of any system of
crimin al justice. The fundamental reason for the exi stence of the crimi-
1 H. Packer, The Limits of the Criminal Sanct ion (Stanford: Stanford Un iversity
Press, 1968). See also K. Ro ach, Due Process and Victims’ Rights: The New L aw
and Politics of Criminal Justic e (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1999).
234
Charter Rights in the Criminal Process 235
nal law is to protect society f rom those individual s whose behaviour
causes serious h arm. The severe sanction of deprivation of liberty and
imprisonment i s justified by t he criminal’s significant departure f rom
the norms of civil society and by the need to puni sh such conduct in
order to protect society from further transgressions.
Our system of crim inal justice has always recogni zed, however,
that crime control is achieved through the assertion of coercive state
power, which inevitably involves risk s of abuse and oppression. To
guard against t hese risks, the crimin al process has evolved a range of
procedural protections, designed to ensure that individuals suspected
of crime are dealt with fairly and humanely. These guarantees, prod-
ucts of both the common law tradition and statutes enacted by Parli a-
ment, include such basic rights as the pre sumption of innocence, the
right to silence, habeas corpus, and the right to be tried by a jur y of
one’s peers. These procedural norms, identified as elements of the “due
process” model, restrain t he exercise of coercive power in a significant
way. They are designed to protect the innocent and to avoid the risk
of wrongful conviction. But they al so benefit the guilty, since they en-
sure that everyone caug ht up in the crimin al proces s should be tre ated
fairly. A part of our trad ition is t he principle that it is better th at ten
gui lty per sons sho uld go fr ee tha n one inno cent person be conv icted. It
is not possible to have a scheme of rights th at protects only those who
are innocent of wrongdoing. Procedural rights often cause consterna-
tion when they assist t he guilty. Yet, that is a price to be paid in a free
society where rights are enjoyed by all individuals.
The criminal justice system is continually striv ing to strike an ap-
propriate balance between crime control and the protection of society
on the one hand, and fairne ss to accused persons and the prevention of
abuse of police powers on the other. The courts have always played an
important role in this exercise. However, by entrenching a number of
procedural rights in the constitution, the Charter of Rights and Freedoms
has increased the courts’ respon sibility to delineate the line between
crime control and due process. In addit ion, other values are relevant
such as the right of privacy and other rights of victims of crime, and
the equality right s of groups such as women, children, and minorities
who may be disproportionately subject to some crimes. While the fun-
damental purp ose of the Canadian criminal justice system rem ains the
protection of society, there can be little question that the result of the
courts’ efforts ha s been to move Canada closer towards the due-process
end of the spectrum. At the same time, many of the Char ter decisions
examined in t his chapter demonstr ate the reality of dialogue between
courts and legislatures under the Charter. Parliament has frequently
the
charter of r ights and fr eedoms
236
responded to the Supreme Court’s due-process decisions w ith new
legislation that while accommod ating due-process rights a lso advances
society’s interests in controlling crime.
A. SECTION 7 AND THE PRINCIPLES OF
FUNDAMENTA L JUSTICE
1) The Fault Element
As noted in chapter 13, a crucial quest ion that was faced in the early
years of the Charter was whether the very general language of section
7 permitted the court s to review the substance of laws or whether judi-
cial review wa s restricted to procedural matters. In Reference Re s. 94(2)
of the Motor Vehicle Act (B.C.),2 the Supreme Court held that “the prin-
ciples of fund amental justice” are not rest ricted to procedural value s
but have substantive content as well. The case involved a fund amental
issue in the cr iminal law, namely, the extent to which moral blamewor-
thiness should be a requi rement for conviction. Criminal offences t ypi-
cally require proof of two elements, har m and fault. Ordinarily, the fact
that harm h as resulted from someone’s conduct is not enough to sup-
port a conviction. To label someone a criminal, we must also be satis-
fied that the indiv idual charged is morally blameworthy. The behaviour
of the individual accu sed of a crime must be shown to have fallen short
of an expected stand ard by intending, or at least foreseeing, the forbid-
den harm. However, the fault requirement is often difficult to prove,
and the legislature m ay judge it to be in the public interest to impose
a sanction without proof of fault of the accused. Re Motor Vehicle Act
involved such a law. It imposed a mandatory penalty of imprisonment
for driving an automobile while one’s licence was under suspen sion.
There were a number of situations that could lead to a licence suspen-
sion without the knowledge of the licence-holder. An individual might
not have even been aware of a licence suspension, and so the re sult
was that a person who had no cr iminal intent could face a mandatory
jail sentence. In the Supreme Court of Canada’s view, such a situation
violated the principles of fundament al justice:
A law that ha s the potential to conv ict a person who has not rea lly
done anythi ng wrong offends t he principles of f undamenta l justice
and, if impri sonment is avail able as a penalty, such a law t hen vio-
2 [1985] 2 S.C.R. 486, 24 D.L.R. (4th) 536 [Re Motor Vehicle Act].

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT